Essay, Research Paper: Taoism

Religion

Free Religion research papers were donated by our members/visitors and are presented free of charge for informational use only. The essay or term paper you are seeing on this page was not produced by our company and should not be considered a sample of our research/writing service. We are neither affiliated with the author of this essay nor responsible for its content. If you need high quality, fresh and competent research / writing done on the subject of Religion, use the professional writing service offered by our company.


Classical Chinese theory of mind is similar to Western "folk
psychology" in that both mirror their respective background view of
language. They differ in ways that fit those folk theories of language. The core
Chinese concept is xin (the heart-mind). As the translation suggests, Chinese
folk psychology lacked a contrast between cognitive and affective states
([representative ideas, cognition, reason, beliefs] versus [desires, motives,
emotions, feelings]). The xin guides action, but not via beliefs and desires. It
takes input from the world and guides action in light of it. Most thinkers share
those core beliefs. Herbert Fingarette argued that Chinese (Confucius at least)
had no psychological theory. Along with the absence of belief-desire explanation
of action, they do not offer psychological (inner mental representation)
explanations of language (meaning). We find neither the focus on an inner world
populated with mental objects nor any preoccupation with questions of the
correspondence of the subjective and objective worlds. Fingarette explained this
as reflecting an appreciation of the deep conventional nature of both linguistic
and moral meaning. He saw this reflected in the Confucian focus on li (ritual)
and its emphasis on sociology and history rather than psychology. The meaning,
the very existence, of a handshake depends on a historical convention. It rests
on no mental acts such as sincerity or intent. The latter may accompany the
conventional act and give it a kind of aesthetic grace, but they do not explain
it. Fingarette overstates the point, of course. It may not be psychologistic in
its linguistic or moral theory, but Confucianism still presupposes a psychology,
albeit not the familiar individualist, mental or cognitive psychology. Its
account of human function in conventional, historical society presupposes some
behavioral and dispositional traits. Most Chinese thinkers indeed appear to
presuppose that humans are social, not egoistic or individualistic. The xin
coordinates our behavior with others. Thinkers differed in their attitude toward
this natural social faculty. Some thought we should reform this tendency and try
harder to become egoists, but most approved of the basic "goodness" of
people. Most also assumed that social discourse influenced how the heart-mind
guides our cooperation. If discourse programs the heart-mind, it must have a
dispositional capacity to internalize the programming. Humans accumulate and
transmit conventional dao-s (guiding discourses—ways). We teach them to our
children and address them to each other. The heart-mind then executes the
guidance in any dao it learns when triggered (e.g., by the sense organs). Again
thinkers differed in their attitude toward this shared outlook. Some thought we
should minimize or eliminate the controlling effect of such conventions on human
behavior. Others focused on how we should reform the social discourse that we
use collectively in programming each other’s xin. Typically, thinkers in the
former group had some theory of the innate or hard-wired programming of the xin.
Some in the latter camp had either a "blank page" or a negative view
of the heart-mind’s innate patterns of response. For some thinkers, the sense
organs delivered a processed input to the heart-mind as a distinction: salty and
sour, sweet and bitter, red or black or white or green and so forth. Most had
thin theories, at best, of how the senses contributed to guidance. While it is
tempting to suppose that they assumed the input was an amorphous flow of "qualia"
that the heart-mind sorted into categories (relevant either to its innate or
social programming). However, given the lack of analysis of the content of the
sensory input, we should probably conservatively assume they took the naďve
realist view that the senses simply make distinctions in the world. We can be
sure only that the xin did trigger reactions to discourse-relevant stimuli.
Reflecting the theory of xin, the implicit theory of language made no
distinction between describing and prescribing. Chinese thinkers assumed the
core function of language is guiding behavior. Representational features served
that prescriptive goal. In executing guidance, we have to identify relevant
"things" in context. If the discourse describes some behavior toward
one’s elder, one needs a way correctly to identify the elder and what counts
as the prescribed behavior. Correct action according to a conventional dao must
also take into account other descriptions of the situation such as ‘urgent’,
‘normal’, etc. These issues lay behind Confucian theories of
"rectifying names." The psychological theory (like the linguistic) did
not take on a sentential form. Classical Chinese language had no
"belief-grammar", i.e., forms such as X believes that P (where P is a
proposition). The closest grammatical counterpart focuses on the term, not the
sentence and point to the different function of xin. Where Westerners would say
"He believes (that) it is good" classical Chinese would either use
"He goods it" or "He, yi (with regard to) it, wei (deems:regards)
good." Similarly zhi (to know) takes noun phrases, not sentences, as
object. The closest counterpart to propositional knowledge would be "He
knows its being (deemed as) good." The xin guides action in the world in
virtue of the categories it assigns to things, but it does not house mental or
linguistic "pictures" of facts. Technically, the attitude was what
philosophers a de re attitude. The "subject" was in the world not in
the mind. The context of use picked out the intended item. The attitude
consisted of projecting the mental category or concept on the actual thing. We
distinguish this functional role best by talking about a disposition rather than
a belief. It is a disposition to assign some reality to a category. The
requisite faculty of the heart-mind (or the senses) is the ability to
discriminate or distinguish T from not-T, e.g., good from bad, human being from
thief. We might, alternately, think of Chinese ‘belief’ and ‘knowledge’
as predicate attitudes rather than propositional attitudes. Predicate attitudes
are the heart-mind’s function. A basic judgment is, thus, neither a picture
nor representation of some metaphysically complex fact. Its essence is picking
out what counts as ‘X’ in the situation (where ‘X’ is a term in the
guiding discourse). The context fixes the object and the heart-mind assigns it
to a relevant category. Hence, Chinese folk theory places a (learned or innate)
ability to make distinctions correctly in following a dao in the central place
Western folk psychology places ideas. They implicitly understood correctness as
conformity to the social-historical norm. One of the projects of some Chinese
philosophers was trying to provide a natural or objective ground of dao. Western
"ideas" are analogous to mental pictographs in a language of thought.
The composite pictures formed out of these mental images (beliefs) were the
mental counterparts of facts. Truth was "correspondence" between the
picture and the fact. Pictures play a role in Chinese folk theory of language
but not of mind. Chinese understood their written characters as having evolved
from pictographs. They had scant reason to think of grammatical strings of
characters as "pictures" of anything. Chinese folk linguistics
recognized that history and community usage determined the reference of the
characters. They did not appeal to the pictographic quality or any associated
mental image individuals might have. Language and conventions are valuable
because they store inherited guidance. The social-historical tradition, not
individual psychology, grounds meaning. Some thinkers became skeptical of claims
about the sages and the "constancy" of their guidance, but they did
not abandon the assumption that public language guides us. Typically, they
either advocated reforming the guiding discourse (dao) or reverting to
"natural," pre-linguistic behavior patterns. Language rested neither
on cognition nor private, individual subjectivity. Chinese philosophy of mind
played mainly an application (execution of instructions) role in Chinese theory
of language. Chinese theory of language centered on counterparts of reference or
denotation. To have mastered a term was for the xin and senses working together
to be able to distinguish or divide realities "correctly."
‘Correctly’ was the rub because the standard of correctness was discourse.
It threatened a regress–we need a discourse to guide our practical
interpretation of discourse. Philosophy of mind played a role in various
attempted solutions. Chinese philosophers mostly agreed (except for innatists)
that actual distinguishing would be relative to past training, experience,
assumptions and situation. However, they did not regard experience as a mental
concept in the classic Western sense of the being a subjective or private
content. An important concept in philosophy of mind was, therefore, de
(virtuosity). One classic formulation identified de as embodied, inner dao. De
though "inner," was more a set of dispositions than a mental content.
The link seemed to be that when we learn a dao’s content, it produces de. Good
de comes from successful teaching of a dao. When you follow dao, you need not
have the discourse "playing" internally. We best view it as the
behavioral ability to conform to the intended pattern of action–the path
(performance dao). It would be "second nature." We may think of de,
accordingly, as both learned and natural. We can distinguish Chinese thought
from Indo-European thought, then, not only in its blending affective and
cognitive functions, but also in its avoiding the nuts and bolts of Western
mind-body analysis. Talk of "inner" and "outer" did
distinguish the psychological from the social, but it did not mean inner was
mental content. The xin has a physical and temporal location and consists of
dispositions to make distinctions in guiding action. It is not a set of
inherently representational "ideas" (mental pictograms). Similarly, we
find no clear counterpart to the Indo-European conception of the faculty of
reason. Euclidean method in geometry and the formulation of the syllogism in
logic informed this Indo-European concept. Absent this apparatus, Chinese
thinkers characterized the heart-mind as either properly or improperly trained,
virtuous, skilled, reliable, etc. Prima facie, however, these were social
standards threatened circularity. The heart-mind required some kind of mastery
of a body of practical knowledge. Chinese thinkers explored norm realism mainly
through an innatist strategy. Innatists sought to picture the heart-mind’s
distinctions as matching "norms" or "moral patterns"
implicit in the natural stasis or harmony of the world. Return to Outline
Historical Developments: The Classical Period Confucius indirectly addressed
philosophy of mind questions in his theory of education. He shaped the moral
debate in a way that fundamentally influenced the classical conception of xin
(heart-mind). Confucius’ discourse dao was the classical syllabus, including
most notably history, poetry and ritual. On one hand, we can think of these as
"training" the xin to proper performance. On the other, the question
of how to interpret the texts into action seemed to require a prior interpretive
capacity of xin. Confucius appealed to a tantalizingly vague intuitive ability
that he called ren (humanity). A person with ren can translate guiding discourse
into performance correctly—i.e., can execute or follow a dao. Confucius left
open whether ren was innate or acquired in study—though the latter seems more
likely to have been his position. It was, in any case, the position of China’s
first philosophical critic, the anti-Confucian Mozi. Again concern with
philosophy of mind was subordinate to Mozi’s normative concerns. He saw moral
character as plastic. Natural human communion (especially our tendency to
"emulate superiors") shaped it. Thus, we could cultivate utilitarian
behavioral tendencies by having social models enunciate and act on a utilitarian
social discourse. The influence of social models would also determine the
interpretation of the discourse. Interpretation takes the form of indexical pro
and con reactions—shi (this:right:assent) and fei (not this:wrong:dissent).
The attitudes when associated with terms pick out the reality (object, action,
etc.) relevant to the discourse guidance. We thus train the heart-mind to make
distinctions that guide its choices and thereby our behavior—specifically in
following a utilitarian symbolic guide. Utilitarian standards also should guide
practical interpretation (execution or performance) of the discourse. At this
point in Chinese thought, the heart-mind became the focus of more systematic
theorizing—much of it in reaction to Mozi’s issues. The moral issue and the
threat of a relativist regress in the picture led to a nativist reaction. On the
one hand, thinkers wanted to imagine ways to free themselves from the implicit
social determinism. On the other, moralists want a more absolute basis for
ethical distinctions and actions. Several thinkers may have joined a trend of
interest in cultivating the heart-mind. Mencius’ theory is the best known
within the moralist trend. He analyzed the heart-mind as consisting of four
natural moral inclinations. These normally mature just as seeds grows into
plants. Therefore, the resulting virtues (‘benevolence’, ‘morality’,
‘ritual’, and ‘knowledge’) were natural. Mencius thus avoided having to
treat the ren intuition as a learned product a social dao. It is a de that
signals a natural dao. This view allowed Mencius to defend Confucian ritual
indirectly against Mozi’s accusation that it relied on an optional and, thus,
changeable tradition. Mencius’ strategy, however, presupposed that a
linguistic dao could either distort or reinforce the heart-mind's innate
program. In principle, we do not need to prop up moral virtue educationally.
Linguistic shaping, other than countering linguistic distortion, therefore, ran
an unnecessary risk. It endangered the natural growth of the moral dispositions.
The shi (this:right:assent) and fei (not this:wrong:dissent) dispositions
necessary for sage-like moral behavior should develop "naturally." His
theory did not imply that we know moral theory at birth, but that they develop
or mature as the physical body does and in response to ordinary moral
situations. The heart-mind functions by issuing shi-fei (this-not this)
directives that are right in the concrete situations in which we find ourselves.
It does not need or generate ethical theory or hypothetical choices. The xin’s
intuitions are situational and implicitly harmonious with nature. A well-known
advocate with the natural spontaneity or freedom motivation was the Taoist,
Laozi. He analyzed the psychology of socialization at a different level.
Learning names was training us to make distinctions and to have desires of what
society considered the appropriate sort. Both the distinctions and the desires
were "right" only according to the conventions of the language
community. Learning language not only meant losing one’s natural spontaneity,
it was and subjecting oneself to control by a social-historical perspective. We
allowed society to control our desires. His famous slogan, wu-wei, enjoined us
to avoid actions motivated by such socialized desires. We achieve that negative
by forgetting socially instilled distinctions—by forgetting language! His
implicit ideal had some affinities with that of Mencius except that his
conception of the "natural" realm of psychological dispositions was
considerably less ambitious in moral terms. Interpreters usually suppose that he
assumed there would be a range of natural desires left even if socialized ones
were "subtracted." These would be enough to sustain small,
non-aggressive, agrarian villages. In them, people would lack the curiosity even
to visit neighboring villages. This "primitivism" still requires that
there is a natural level of harmonious impulses to action, but not nearly enough
to sustain Mencius’ unified moral empire. The LATER MOHISTS became skeptical
of the neutral status of these allegedly "natural" heart-mind states.
They noted that even a thief may claim that his behavior was natural. They
watered down the conventionalism of Mozi by appealing to objectively accessible
similarities and differences in nature. Our language ought to reflect these
clusters of similarity. They did little epistemology especially of the senses,
but supposedly, like Mozi, would have appealed to the testimony ordinary people
relying on their "eyes and ears." Others (See ZHUANGZI) insisted that
any apparent patterns of similarity and difference were always perspectival and
relative to some prior purpose, standards or value attitude. Linguistics did
shape heart-mind attitudes but neither reliably or accurately carves the world
into its real parts. The Later Mohists had given a cluster of definitions of zhi
(to know). One of these seemed close to consciousness—or rather to point to
the lack of any such concept. Zhi was the capacity to know. In dreaming the zhi
did not zhi and we took (something) as so. They analyzed the key function of the
heart-mind as the capacity to discriminate linguistic intention. Zhuangzi takes
a step beyond Laozi in his theory of emotions. Zhuangzi discusses the passions
and emotions that were raw, pre-social inputs from reality. He suggested a
pragmatic attitude toward them—we cannot know what purpose they have, but
without them, there would be no reference for the "I." Without the
'I', there would be neither choosing nor objects of choice. Like Hume, he argued
that while we have these inputs and feel there must be some organizing
"true ruler," we get no input (qing) from any such ruler. We simply
have the inputs themselves (happiness, anger, sorrow, joy, fear). We cannot
suppose that the physical heart is such a ruler, because it is no more natural
than the other organs and joints of the body. Training and history condition a
heart’s judgments. Ultimately, even Mencius’ shi-fei (this-not this) are
input to the xin. Our experience introduces them relative to our position and
past assumptions. They are not objective or neutral judgments. XUNZI also
concentrated on issues related to philosophy of mind though in the context of
moral and linguistic issues. He initiated some important and historically
influential developments in the classical theory. His most famous (and textually
suspect) doctrine is "human nature is evil." While he clearly wanted
to distance himself from Mencius, the slogan at best obscures the deep affinity
between their respective views of human nature and mind. Xunzi seems to have
drawn both from the tradition advocating cultivating heart-mind and from the
focused theory of language. This produced a tense hybrid theory that filled out
the original Confucian picture on how conventions and language program the
heart-mind. Xunzi made the naturalism explicit. Human guiding discourse takes
place in the context of a three-tier universe—tian (heaven-nature) di
(earth-sustenance) and ren (the social realm). He gave humans a special place in
the ‘chain of nature,' but not based on reason. Animals shared the capacity
for zhi (knowledge). What distinguishes humans is their yi (morality) which is
grounded on the ability to bian (distinguish). Presumably, the latter ability is
unique among animals with knowledge because it is short-hand for the ability to
construct and abide by conventions–conventional distinctions or language. One
of Xunzi’s naturalistic justifications for Confucian conventional rituals is
economic. Ritual distinctions guide people’s desires so that society can
manage scarcity. Only those with high status will learn to seek scarce goods.
His departure from Mencius thus seems to lie in seeing human morality as more
informed or "filled-out" by historical conventional distinctions.
These are the products of reflection and artifice, not nature. However, in other
ways Xunzi seems to edge closer to Mencius. He also presents ritual as part of
the structure of the world—implicit in the heaven-earth natural context. One
natural line of explanation is this: while thought creates the correct
conventions, nature sets the concrete conditions of scarcity and human traits
that determine what conventions will be best for human flourishing. Return to
Outline Historical Developments: Han Cosmology The onset of the philosophical
dark age, brought on by Qin Dynasty repression followed by Han dynasty policies
resulted in a bureaucratic, obscurant Confucian orthodoxy. The Qin thus buried
the technical ideas informing philosophy of mind along with the active thinkers
who understood them. The ontology of the eclectic scholasticism that emerged was
essentially religious and superstitious. It was, however, overtly materialist
(assuming Qi (ether, matter) is material). So the implicit philosophy of mind of
the few philosophically inclined thinkers during the period tended toward a
vague materialism. The Han further developed the five-element (five phases)
version of materialism. They postulated a correlative pentalogy linking
virtually every system of classification that occurred to them. The scheme
included the organs of the body and the virtues. Interpretation and analysis of
"correlative" reasoning is a controversial subject. From here, the
mental correlations look more like a frequency selection from the psychological
lexicon than a product of philosophical reflection, observation or causal
theory. The Yin-yang analysis also had mental correlates. Following Xunzi,
Orthodox Han Confucians tended to treat qing (reality:desires) as yin (typically
negative). The yang (value positive) counterpart was xing (human moral nature).
The most important development of the period was the emergence a compromise
Confucian view of mind’s role in morality. It eventually informed and
dominated the scholastic Neo-Confucianism of the much later Sung to Qing
dynasties. The small book known as the Doctrine of the Mean gave it an
influential formulation. It presents the heart-mind as a homeostasis-preserving
input output device. The heart-mind starts in a state of tranquillity. The
account leaves open whether this is a result of ideally structured moral input,
resolution of inner conflicts, or the absence of (distorting) content. Xunzi’s
view of the empty, unified and still mind seems the proximate ancestor of the
latter aspect of the view. The vagueness, conveniently, makes Mencius’
doctrines fit it as well. The input is a perturbation from the outer world. The
output, the heart-mind’s action-guiding response, restores harmony to the
world and the inner state to tranquillity. If the inner state prior to the input
is not tranquil, the response will not restore harmony to the real situation.
Han Confucianism filled out this cosmic view of this black-box interaction
between heart-mind and world harmony using qi materialism. Qi is a rather more a
blend of energy and matter than pure matter—translations such as
"life-force" bring out an essential connection with vitality. This
makes it more appropriate for a cosmology that links the active heart-mind with
the changing world. Qi was the single constituting element of spirits and ghosts
as well. Wang Ch’ung’s skeptical, reductive application of qi theory focused
on shen (spirit-energy). He did not view its consequences for heart-mind as
particularly iconoclastic. It still lacked a notion of "consciousness"
independent of zhi (know). (Our zhi, he argued, stops when we are asleep and so
almost certainly it does when we are dead.) His arguments that nature had no
intentional purposes illustrated his reductive behaviorism—if it has neither
eyes nor ears, then it cannot have zhi (purposes or intentions). This argument
would hardly make sense if he had the familiar Western concept of consciousness.
Similarly, he argues that the five virtues are in the five organs so when the
organs are dead and gone, the virtues disappear with them. Return to Outline
Historical Developments: Buddhist Philosophy of Mind The next developments are
related to the introduction of Buddhist mental concepts into China. Most
accounts credit a movement dubbed "Neo-Taoism" with "paving the
way" for this radical change in philosophy of mind. Wangbi’s Neo-Taoist
system was explicitly a cosmology more than a theory of mind, but
interpretations tend to read it epistemically. Wangbi addressed the metaphysical
puzzle of the relation of being and non-being. (See YOU-WU) He postulated
non-being as the "basic substance." Non-being produced being. He
dubbed this obscure relationship as "substance and function."
Interpretations almost inevitably explain this on the analogy to Kant’s
Noumenon and Phenomenon. As noted, Wangbi had few epistemological interests, but
the analysis did have implications for heart-mind theory. He applied the
metaphysical scheme to his Confucian slogan–"Sage within, king
without." The mind was empty "within" while the behaviors were in
perfect conformity with the Confucian ritual dao. This tilts the Taoist
tradition toward the "emptiness" reading of the black-box analysis of
heart-mind. Wangbi also placed li (principle) in a more central explanatory
position. This paved the way for its use in translating Buddhism’s sentence or
law-like ‘dharma’. It played roles in both Buddhist epistemology and theory
of mind. In sparse pre-Han usage, li was objective tendencies in thing-kinds.
(Intuitionists and naturalists took them to be the valid norm for that
kind—species relative bits of dao.) Wangbi gave it a more essentialist reading
in the context of the Book of Changes. He postulated a li guiding the mixtures
and transformations of yin and yang. One should be able to bypass the complexity
of the system by isolating and understanding its li. Buddhism introduced
revolutionary changes into Chinese heart-mind conceptual scheme. The original
Indo-European religion probably originated the familiar Western phenomenalism
(consciousness, experience-based mentalism). Indian philosophy came complete
with the familiar Western sentential analyses, mental content and cognitive
emphasis (belief and knowing-that). It even mimicked the subject-predicate
syllogism and the familiar epistemic and metaphysical subjective-objective
dualism. It introduced a semantic (eternal) truth predicate into Chinese thought
along with a representational view of the function of both mind and language.
Reason/intellect and emotion/desire formed a basic opposition in Buddhist
psychological analysis. An inner idea-world parallels (or replaces) the ordinary
world of objects. Soul and mind are roughly interchangeable and familiar
arguments for immortality suggest both metaphysical dualism and mental
transcendence or superiority over the physical. It conceptually links reality
(knowledge, reason) to permanence and appearance (illusion, experience) to
change. A universal chain of causation was a central explanatory device and a
mark of dependence and impermanence. Two caveats are in order, however. First,
although Buddhism introduced a dualist conceptual scheme, many schools
(arguably) denied the dualism so formulated and rejected any transcendent
‘self’. Second, it is unclear how well the philosophy of mind was generally
understood and whether much of it actually "took" in China. One of the
early and notoriously unsuccessful schools was the "Consciousness
only" school (translated as "Only Heart-mind") which translated
the idealism of Yogacara Buddhism. The Yogacara analysis was Hume-like in
denying that anything linked the infinitesimal "moments of awareness"
into a real self. Scholars tend to blame its demise, however, as much on its
objectionable moral features (its alleged Hinayana or elitist failure to
guarantee universal salvation) as on its conceptual innovations. The most
successful schools were those that seemed to eschew theory of any kind—like
Zen (Ch’an) or Pure Land Buddhism—or those that opted for intuitive,
mystical simplicity (Tian T’ai and Hua Yen). The most important conceptual
legacy of Buddhism, therefore, seems to be the changed role and importance of
the character li (principle). In Buddhism it served a wide range of important
sentential and mental functions. It facilitated the translation of ‘law’,
‘truth’, and ‘reason’. Neo-Confucianism would take it over (with
notoriously controversial implications) as key concept in its philosophy of
mind. Return to Outline Historical Developments: Neo-Confucianism
Neo-Confucianism is a Western name for a series of schools in which philosophy
of mind played a central role. Scholars (somewhat controversially) present these
schools as motivated by an anti-foreignism that sought to resurrect indigenous
classical systems. These had lain dormant for six-hundred odd years when the
freshness of Buddhism started to attract the attention of China's intellectuals.
Resurrecting Confucianism required providing it with an alternative to Buddhist
metaphysics. For this, they drew on ch'i metaphysics, the black-box homeostasis
preserving analysis of heart-mind, Wang Pi's and Buddhism's li and Mencius'
classical theory of the inherent goodness of heart-mind. The intricacies of
Neo-Confucian systems are too rich to analyze in detail here. The earliest
versions focused on the notion of qi linkage between the heart-mind and the
world influenced by our action. They characterized the tranquil state of the
black-box as void. The school of li criticized that analysis as too Zen-like.
(This was a typical and damning charge to participants in this movement,
although a Zen period in one’s development of thought was a common pattern
among Neo-Confucians.) The li school insisted that any adequate account of
heart-mind had to give it an original moral content. It did this by postulating
an interdependent and inseparable dualism of li and qi. The li permeates the
heart and all of reality, which is composed of qi. The most tempting (and
common) elaboration uses the Platonic distinction of form and content, but that
analysis teeters on the edge of incoherence. The school fell back on dividing
the human mind from some transcendental or metaphysical Tao-mind. This made it
dubious as a theory of mind at all—in the ordinary sense. It essentially
became a metaphysics in which heart-mind was a cosmic force. One way of
understanding the motivation that drove the otherwise puzzling metaphysical
gymnastics links philosophy of mind and ethics. Neo-Confucians were searching
for the metaphysical system such that anyone so viewing the cosmos and one's
place in it would reliably do what was right. The goal was having the
metaphysical outlook of the sage. The criterion of right and wrong was that the
sage's mind would so judge it. If we could replicate the outlook, we would be
sage-like in our attitudes–including both beliefs and motivations. The effect
on motivation and behavior was more important than the theoretical coherence of
the system. The complexity of moral choice and human motivation required so many
perturbations into their account of the proposed system that it became an almost
infinitely flexible rationalization for intuitionism. Mencian optimism about
innate heart-mind dispositions proved an uncomfortable legacy. If human nature
and the heart-mind are innately and spontaneously moral, it was unclear why we
require such mental gymnastics to cultivate and condition the dispositions. They
portrayed the li as inherently good in all things, but somehow humans, alone in
all of nature, might fail to conform to its own natural norms. The attempt to
explain this via the li qi dualism flounders on the metaphysical principle that
the dualism pervades all things. Despite this well known (and intractable)
Confucian problem of evil, the school again became the Medieval orthodoxy.
Office holding required being able to parrot the view in considerable detail to
show their moral character. The school of Heart-mind was a rebellion against
that orthodoxy. We best understand this rival as a species of normative,
objective idealism. It saw the actual heart-mind as li and therefore inherently
good. The xin projects that li onto the world in the act of categorizing and
dividing it into types. Thus our normative, (phenomenal) world is good but that
good is a function of the mind. Moral categorization and action are a
simultaneous and combined responses of the heart-mind to the perturbations or
the disharmonies we encounter. The analysis of mind is functional—there is no
goodness of the mind separate from the goodness of its categorizing and acting.
Knowing is acting. The school of heart-mind somewhat gingerly accepted the
implication of their Mencian heritage. There is no evil. I say
"gingerly" because whether one should formulate or teach this
conclusion or not is itself a choice that the mind must assess for its
contextual value. In itself, as it were, the heart-mind is beyond good and evil.
Others, hence, criticized school of heart-mind was for its own Zen-like
implications. Any moderately clever student could figure out that whatever he
chose to do was right (c.f., Zhuangzi’s initial criticism's of Mencian
idealism). They, in turn, criticized the Buddhist character of their rival's
assumptions that some kind of state of mind (enlightenment, realization) would
magically result in sagehood. The moralistic name-calling of this
inter-Confucian debate sapped further development of theory of mind. That
coupled with its irrational optimism in the face of growing awareness of the
vulnerability and weakness of China to resist Western and Japanese military and
political power resulted first in mildly more materialistic and utilitarian
systems. Eventually intellectuals developed a wholesale interest in the next
Indo-European thought invasion, which took the form of Marxism. Maoist theory of
mind was an unstable mixture of Marxist economic and materialist reductionism
and traditional Chinese optimism. The right political attitude (typically that
of the part member) would give good communists spectacular moral power and
infallible situational intuitions about how to solve social problems. Again, the
obvious failure in the face of irrational theoretical optimism has produced a
general antipathy to idealizations. One can guess that the next phase, like the
Buddhist phase, will be one of borrowing and blending. However, the current
skepticism about the general outlines of folk psychology in the West and its
essentially alien character probably will keep Chinese theory of heart-mind
distinctively Chinese. BibliographyChan, Wing tsit. 1986 Neo-Confucian Terms Explained (New York: Columbia
University Press) pp. xi-277. Fingarette, Herbert. 1972 Confucius The Secular as
Sacred . Graham, Angus. 1964 "The Place of Reason in the Chinese
Philosophical Tradition," in Raymond Dawson (ed.), The Legacy of China pp.
28-56. Graham, Angus. 1967 "The Background of the Mencian Theory of Human
Nature," Tsing Hua Journal of Chinese Studies 6/1, 2 pp. 215-274. Graham,
Angus. 1989 Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China (La
Salle, IL: Open Court) . Hansen, Chad. 1991 "Should the Ancient Masters
Value Reason?," in Henry Rosemont (ed.), Chinese Texts and Philosophical
Contexts: Essays Dedicated to A. C. Graham (La Salle, IL: Open Court) pp.
179-209. Hansen, Chad. 1992 A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought (New York: Oxford
University Press) pp. xv-448. Hansen, Chad. 1993 "Term Belief in
Action," in Lenk et al (ed.), Epistemological Issues in Chinese Philosophy
(Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and Cu) pp. 45-68. Hansen, Chad.
12/30/95 "Qing (Emotions) in Pre-Buddhist Chinese Thought," in Joel
Marks and Roger T. Ames (ed.), Emotions in Asian Thought (State University of
New York Press) pp. 181-211. Munro, Donald J.. 1969 The Concept of Man in Early
China (Stanford: Stanford University Press) . Munro, Donald J.. 1977 The Concept
of Man in Contemporary China (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press) pp. xii,
248. Munro, Donald J.. 1985 in Donald J. Munro (ed.), Individualism and Holism:
Studies in Confucian and Taoist Values (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press)
. Munro, Donald J.. 1988 Images of Human Nature: a Sung Portrait (Princeton:
Princeton University Press) pp. 322. Schwartz, Benjamin. 1985 The World of
Thought in Ancient China (Cambridge: Harvard University Press).
0
0
Good or bad? How would you rate this essay?
Help other users to find the good and worthy free term papers and trash the bad ones.
Like this term paper? Vote & Promote so that others can find it

Get a Custom Paper on Religion:

Free papers will not meet the guidelines of your specific project. If you need a custom essay on Religion: , we can write you a high quality authentic essay. While free essays can be traced by Turnitin (plagiarism detection program), our custom written papers will pass any plagiarism test, guaranteed. Our writing service will save you time and grade.




Related essays:

0
0
Religion / Taoism
It is always present in you. You can use it anyway you want. -- Lao-tzu Taoism is one of the two great philosophical and religious traditions that originated in China. The other philosophy native to ...
3262 views
0 comments
0
0
Religion / Taoism
Taoism was first thought of by Lao Tzu. He thought that if you seek order and harmony and observe that nothing in nature strives for fame, power, and wisdom. Tao means "The way" or the univ...
2405 views
0 comments
0
0
Religion / Taoism
In order to go into Taoism at all, we must begin by being in the frame of mind in which it can understood. You cannot force yourself into this frame of mind, anymore than you can smooth rippled water...
2712 views
0 comments
0
0
"Before the world was made, he chose us, chose us in Christ, to be holy and spotless, and to live through love in his presence, determining that we should become his adopted sons, through Jesus ...
2403 views
0 comments
0
1
To escape punishment for killing an Egyptian, Moses ran away to Midian, where he met and married the daughter of a shepherd. During that time, the king of Egypt died, and the Israelites called out to...
3479 views
0 comments